« Children are not, qua
children, innocent. We all have been children and know –unless we
prefer to forget- how little innocent we were, what determined
efforts of indoctrination it took to make us into innocents, how
often we tried to escape from the staging-camp of childhood and how
implacably we were herded back. Nor do we inherently posses dignity.
We are certainly born without dignity, and we spend enough time by
ourselves, hidden from the eyes of others, doing the things that we
do when we are by ourselves, to know how little of it we can honestly
lay claim to. We also see enough of animals concerned for their
dignity (cats, for instance) to know how comical pretensions to
dignity can be.
Innocence is a state in which we try
to maintain our children ;dignity is a state we claim for
ourselves. Affronts to the innocence of our children or to the
dignity of our persons are attacks not upon our essential being but
upon constructs –constructs by which we live, but constructs
nevertheless. This is not to say that affronts to our innocence or
dignity are not real affronts, but that the outrage with which we
respond to them is not real, in a sense of not being sincerely felt.
The infringements are real ; what is infringed, however, is not
our essence, but a foundational fiction to which we more or less
wholeheartedly subscribe, a fiction that may well be indispensable
for a just society, namely, that human beings have a dignity that
sets them apart from animals and consequently protects them from
being treated like animals. (it is even possible that we may look
forward to a day when animals will have theit own dignity ascribed to
them, and the ban will be reformulated as a ban on treating a living
creature like a thing,.)
The fiction of dignity helps to define
humanity and the status of humanity helps to define human rights.
There is thus a real sense in which an affront to our dignity strikes
at our rights. Yet when, outraged at such affront, we stand for our
rigghts and demand redress, we would do well to remember how
unsubstancial the dignity is on which those rights are based.
Forgetting where our dignity comes from, we may fall into a posture
as comical as that of the irate censor..
Life, says Erasmus’s Folly is
theater : we each have lines to say and a part to play. One kind of
actor, recognizing that is is in a play, will go on playing
nervertheless ; another kind of actor, shocked to find he is
participating in a illusion, will try to step off the stage and out
of the play. The second actor is mistaken. For there is nothing
outside the theater, no alternative life we can join instead. The
show is, so to speak, the only show in town. All one can do is to go
on playing one’s part, though perhaps with a new awareness, a comic
awareness.
We thus arrive at a pair of Erasmian
paradoxes. A dignity worthy of of respect is a dignity without
dignity (which is quite different from unconscious or unaffected
dignity); an innoccence worthy of of respect is an innocence without
innocence. As for respect itself, it is tempting to suggest that this
is a superfluous concept, though for the workings of the theater of
life it may turn to be indispensable. True respect is a variety of
love and may be subsumed under love ; to respect someone means, inter
alia, to forgive that person an innocence that, outside the theater,
would be false, a dignity that would be risible ».
No comments:
Post a Comment